CodyHuyanSecondEssay 5 - 27 May 2024 - Main.CodyHuyan
|
|
META TOPICPARENT | name="SecondEssay" |
| |
< < | Justifications for Nationality Based Rights and Obligations | > > | [Revised] Justifications for Nationality Based Rights and Obligations | | -- By CodyHuyan - 22 Apr 2024 | | Why do people choose to obey laws of another country? | |
> > | While nationality-based social contrarian theory sufficiently answers the obligation question, it fails to adequately explain the choice question. One must still make a conscious choice to perform its obligations. In cases where there are less enforcement mechanisms, which can be the case for visitors in a foreign country (i.e. no extradition, short stay lowering chances of being caught), there are more opportunities for one to not obey the law while facing no negative consequence. So why do people still choose to obey laws of a foreign host country, even if the law is different from their home country or that they don’t agree with it? | | | |
< < | Conclusion | > > | Some theorists, such as Yael Tamir, have put forth an associative obligations theory to explain voluntarily assumption of burdens, arguing that the willingness to assume legal obligation derive from people’s sense of responsibility towards members of the community with which they associate. Yet, travelling doesn’t necessarily change one’s association. Travelling to China and choosing to obey their law doesn’t mean I now associate with the Chinese community. Conversely, my association with the U.S. also does not negate the legal obligation upon me to follow Chinese law. | | | |
> > | Perhaps, an alternative cosmopolitan theory offers a better justification for the choice question. Rather than independent entities, the world should be viewed as one exhaustive community, where birthright citizenship is nothing more than the same type of contingency that race, gender, or social class are. Nationality, then, is simply a governance mechanism to better facilitate and enforce the rights and obligations each person owes as a citizen of the world. Ultimately, irrespective of individual backgrounds and nationality, we all should be owed a common baseline set of rights as human. This set of rights doesn’t denote a universal moral standard. Rather, each nation exists to cultivate their own unique culture and standards. This baseline set of rules narrowly indicates a bottom line of decency and care that all people should be entitled to, i.e. not being physically hurt by another without a justifiable cause. To respect each other’s culture and rules when temporarily intruding upon one’s community is part of that baseline decency we owe each other. Thus even when there are discrepancies and disagreements with foreign law, people often choose to obey it as long as the disagreement is not material. | | | |
> > | The Role of Nationality | | | |
< < |
You need a draft that is not more than 1,000 words. This is at least 8% too long. | > > | In addition to its pragmatic function as the source of legal authority, nations also exist to formulate communities and promote cultural diversity. Just like race or religion based communities within a country can have their own unique rules and preferences additional to legal national requirements, each nation also creates communal norms above the baseline mandated by the world at large. These cultures and norms inform the fundamental values of an individual. When one faces discrepancies or disagreement with laws in a foreign country, the materiality of such discrepancy and whether it is “worth it” to break the law for what they believe to be righteous is dictated by their nationality and values associated. Worthiness obviously requires a more comprehensive inquiry into the costs of disobedience, which is not addressed here, but the anticipated utility from disobedience is largely influenced by the social, culture, and political backgrounds that one grows up in. While nationality is not the only factor as religion, race, social class, or any similar contingencies will have a bearing on it, it plays a foundational role as a nation’s rules of law contours the outer boundaries of one’s perspective. | | | |
< < | It should not be hard to cut. When choosing to re-use prior work, you should have decided to rewrite it completely. This isn't a book report about Yael Tamir anymore. Your draft should frame a question sharply. From a lawyer's perspective, which is the one you now inhabit, this is an inquiry into the source of our obligation to obey law, and how "nationality" relates to it. Rather than being a discussion about social contractarianism and liberal theory, it asks why I obey Dutch law when I am in the Netherlands, even though I have a US passport and obey US law when I am at home. The answer is not that I belong to the Dutch when I am there, or that I have associated Dutch-ness, or that I am afraid of being sent to Dutch prison or being beaten by a Dutch policeman. But those might explain why I obey Chinese law in China, or why I broke Soviet law in the Soviet Union. You learned something once, and here we are using that learning in a new way another time. Let's try a draft that acknowledges more fully what is new.
| > > | I choose to obey China’s ban on marijuana, but maybe, if my freedom of speech is on the line instead, I will choose to break the law. | |
|
|
CodyHuyanSecondEssay 4 - 27 May 2024 - Main.CodyHuyan
|
|
META TOPICPARENT | name="SecondEssay" |
| | Introduction | |
< < | We live in a world where our rights and obligations are defined by national borders. Nationality is our form of membership in a country. With the obtainment of membership comes rights and obligations. These rights and obligations are protected by rules of law unique to each nation. U.S. nationals are obligated to pay taxes and social security used to benefit members of the community, but these benefits are not extended to individuals in other nations. What justifies these nationality-based rights and obligations? This is the question Yael Tamir identifies in the modern liberal theory. | > > | I am a citizen of California and smoke marijuana regularly (I don’t really). Recreational use is legal there. When I visit China, I don’t use any cannabis products because any use of marijuana is strictly prohibited. I don’t believe that smoking weed should be illegal, but I choose to follow Chinese law nonetheless when I travel there. Why do I need to or choose to obey Chinese law as a U.S. citizen? | | | |
< < | Yael Tamir's Associative Obligation Framework and Its Inherent Dangers | > > | It is necessary to address the need and choice questions separately. Host countries impose a legal obligation upon visiting foreigners to abide by domestic laws, but foreigners practically have a choice not to. Especially when there are no extradition agreements with the host country and the visitor is only present for a short timeframe, enforcement of domestic law can be difficult, creating opportunities for people to break the law while facing no consequences. Yet, even with lower deterrence effects, most people still choose to obey the law. The origin of such voluntariness to obey law that one doesn’t necessarily agrees with warrants an analysis separate from the theory through which a legal obligation is imposed. | | | |
< < | Tamir suggests that liberal theory itself is not enough to provide an answer and points to national ideals hidden in the liberal agenda. In exploration for an answer, she considers the contractarian approach commonly adopted by liberal philosophers in their perspective on modern liberal societies. Yet, she soon rejects the approach as an explanation for national obligations. Criteria of state membership prioritize birthright and kinship rather than individual consent. Since “political obligations in a liberal state are not assumed in as free and rational a process as is commonly argued” (Tamir 1995, p.130), the voluntary assumption of obligations does not necessarily imply consent. Thus, the social contract theory cannot fill in the missing component in the social contract theory. | > > | Why are people obligated to obey laws of another country? | | | |
< < | Yael Tamir suggests that the only way to justify the assumption of obligations in liberal theory is to view liberal welfare states as communities that generate associative obligations, which derive from feelings of membership, rather than contractarian entities (Tamir 1995, p.130). There is a difference in formally being a member and feeling like a member: “The fact that we are citizens of a particular state, however is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for creating obligations. […] The second statement (‘X feels that he is a member’) is the one that carries the thrust of the associative argument, suggesting that one is bound by obligations because one sees oneself as a member” (p.134-135). Although the associative approach reasonably explains the formation of the sense of community required for the voluntary assumption of mutual burdens on a philosophical approach, dangers of its realistic application cannot be ignored. | > > | Another way to frame the need question is where does a country obtain the legitimacy and authority to impose and enforce their domestic laws on foreigners within its border? While I believe that the social contrarian theory adopted by many liberal theorists fail to address the choice question, it does provide an explanation for the source of authority of a country. Social contrarian theory purports that people obey the law because they implicitly agreed to a social contract to do so. Nationality is our acceptance of the social contract. With nationality comes the enjoyment of certain benefits, what we call rights, in exchange for forfeiting certain personal interests, which we name obligations. The ability to travel to other countries is one benefit that one’s nationality offers, although with varying levels of convenience. In exchange for such benefit, countries mutually agree to legal authority over each other’s visiting citizens. On an individual level, acceptance to the social contract of the hosting country effectuates through one’s obtainment of Visa and actual entry. Travelers enjoys hospitality, safety, and other resources from the hosting country. In exchange, they agree to abide by the domestic law and for host country’s authority to enforce the law. | | | |
< < | The freedom to assume and discard membership and obligation is inherently dangerous to domestic governance and the enforcement of the rule of law. Tamir would agree that obligations to a nation include obedience to rules of law that are reasonably just (p.131). Suppose a Chinese American feels alienated in the United States and chooses to pledge allegiance to China instead, despite remaining a U.S. citizen formally. Following Tamir’s associative framework, he would be released from any obligations to the U.S. based on his feelings. Such discharge from U.S. obligations justifies the alienated Chinese American to disobey American laws in areas that differ from Chinese laws. This implication endangers the rights of other members that a nation is obliged to protect, as it opens the door to exploitation of jurisdictional differences of law. Rationalization of discharge from obligations to obey laws of a country that one is still a formal member of essentially invents a new form of legal defense that cannot be proven evidentiarily but must be accepted by the court. Whenever facing a charge that may be legal in another country, the defendant can simply claim that they had assumed obligations there at the time of the offense. Neither the timing nor accuracy can be evidentiarily accountable. | > > | Why do people choose to obey laws of another country? | | | |
< < | Furthermore, the functioning of associative obligation framework requires accountability for the accuracy of laws of other nations, which is difficult to achieve in reality. The previous scenario of jurisdictional exploitation presumes a truthful application of another jurisdiction’s law. But what if the defendant simply chose a county of which the judge is unfamiliar with the law? Adjudication of offenses under the associative framework essentially require judges and attorneys to understand the language and laws of all countries to produce just judgments, which is an impossible ask.
An Alternative Cosmopolitan Approach
An alternative, perhaps, is to approach the question from a cosmopolitan point of view. Rather than independent entities, the world should be viewed as one exhaustive community, where birthright citizenship is nothing more than the same type of contingency that race, gender, or social class are. Nationality, then, is simply a governance mechanism to better facilitate and enforce the rights and obligations each person owes as a citizen of the world. Ultimately, irrespective of individual backgrounds and nationality, we all should be owed a common baseline of rights as human. Similar to race or religion base communities within a nation, who may hold themselves to a higher moral standard, only owe fellow citizens outside their group what the law requires; some countries may impose higher legal obligations upon their members but this does not necessarily interfere with the baseline that the world as a whole requires.
The approach seems to cure certain flaws of the associative obligation framework. The legal baseline adopted in the world community must necessarily be at the level of the lowest bar posed by any single “country”, or a bar uniformly agreed upon. Either way, a uniform basis of rights and obligations would eliminate legal enforcement difficulties created by jurisdictional differences. “Countries” may certainly opt to maintain a higher obligation requirement of its members, but such requirement will be merely moral and enforced by community norms. However, since no country will have a lower requirement than the uniform basis, freedom to assume obligations based on feelings of association will not become a fundamental vulnerability to social orders. | | Conclusion | |
< < | Though, the cosmopolitan approach is not free of flaws. The uniformity of law inevitably points towards a binding global enforcement agency. Elimination of jurisdictional exploitations require consistent interpretation, application, and enforcement of law, which would be best achieved by legislative and judicial bodies binding on every member country of the global community. Although guiding international organizations exist now, the envisioned governing mechanism requires another level of international cooperation and relinquishment of power from the superpowers, rendering the feasibility of the cosmopolitan approach debatable. Even if such governing mechanism can be employed, preservation of voices and rights of minorities and small “countries” will be continued issues just like racial and gender equality are now. But, perhaps, this attempt to justify nationality-based rights and obligations may motivate further explorations of the cosmopolitan approach and its realistic implications to present a solution to some issue we are currently facing in the world. | > > | | |
You need a draft that is not more than 1,000 words. This is at least 8% too long. |
|
CodyHuyanSecondEssay 3 - 18 May 2024 - Main.EbenMoglen
|
|
META TOPICPARENT | name="SecondEssay" |
| |
< < | It is strongly recommended that you include your outline in the body of your essay by using the outline as section titles. The headings below are there to remind you how section and subsection titles are formatted. | | Justifications for Nationality Based Rights and Obligations | | Though, the cosmopolitan approach is not free of flaws. The uniformity of law inevitably points towards a binding global enforcement agency. Elimination of jurisdictional exploitations require consistent interpretation, application, and enforcement of law, which would be best achieved by legislative and judicial bodies binding on every member country of the global community. Although guiding international organizations exist now, the envisioned governing mechanism requires another level of international cooperation and relinquishment of power from the superpowers, rendering the feasibility of the cosmopolitan approach debatable. Even if such governing mechanism can be employed, preservation of voices and rights of minorities and small “countries” will be continued issues just like racial and gender equality are now. But, perhaps, this attempt to justify nationality-based rights and obligations may motivate further explorations of the cosmopolitan approach and its realistic implications to present a solution to some issue we are currently facing in the world. | |
> > |
You need a draft that is not more than 1,000 words. This is at least 8% too long.
It should not be hard to cut. When choosing to re-use prior work, you should have decided to rewrite it completely. This isn't a book report about Yael Tamir anymore. Your draft should frame a question sharply. From a lawyer's perspective, which is the one you now inhabit, this is an inquiry into the source of our obligation to obey law, and how "nationality" relates to it. Rather than being a discussion about social contractarianism and liberal theory, it asks why I obey Dutch law when I am in the Netherlands, even though I have a US passport and obey US law when I am at home. The answer is not that I belong to the Dutch when I am there, or that I have associated Dutch-ness, or that I am afraid of being sent to Dutch prison or being beaten by a Dutch policeman. But those might explain why I obey Chinese law in China, or why I broke Soviet law in the Soviet Union. You learned something once, and here we are using that learning in a new way another time. Let's try a draft that acknowledges more fully what is new.
| |
You are entitled to restrict access to your paper if you want to. But we all derive immense benefit from reading one another's work, and I hope you won't feel the need unless the subject matter is personal and its disclosure would be harmful or undesirable.
To restrict access to your paper simply delete the "#" character on the next two lines: |
|
CodyHuyanSecondEssay 2 - 22 Apr 2024 - Main.CodyHuyan
|
|
META TOPICPARENT | name="SecondEssay" |
It is strongly recommended that you include your outline in the body of your essay by using the outline as section titles. The headings below are there to remind you how section and subsection titles are formatted. | | An alternative, perhaps, is to approach the question from a cosmopolitan point of view. Rather than independent entities, the world should be viewed as one exhaustive community, where birthright citizenship is nothing more than the same type of contingency that race, gender, or social class are. Nationality, then, is simply a governance mechanism to better facilitate and enforce the rights and obligations each person owes as a citizen of the world. Ultimately, irrespective of individual backgrounds and nationality, we all should be owed a common baseline of rights as human. Similar to race or religion base communities within a nation, who may hold themselves to a higher moral standard, only owe fellow citizens outside their group what the law requires; some countries may impose higher legal obligations upon their members but this does not necessarily interfere with the baseline that the world as a whole requires. | |
> > | The approach seems to cure certain flaws of the associative obligation framework. The legal baseline adopted in the world community must necessarily be at the level of the lowest bar posed by any single “country”, or a bar uniformly agreed upon. Either way, a uniform basis of rights and obligations would eliminate legal enforcement difficulties created by jurisdictional differences. “Countries” may certainly opt to maintain a higher obligation requirement of its members, but such requirement will be merely moral and enforced by community norms. However, since no country will have a lower requirement than the uniform basis, freedom to assume obligations based on feelings of association will not become a fundamental vulnerability to social orders.
Conclusion
Though, the cosmopolitan approach is not free of flaws. The uniformity of law inevitably points towards a binding global enforcement agency. Elimination of jurisdictional exploitations require consistent interpretation, application, and enforcement of law, which would be best achieved by legislative and judicial bodies binding on every member country of the global community. Although guiding international organizations exist now, the envisioned governing mechanism requires another level of international cooperation and relinquishment of power from the superpowers, rendering the feasibility of the cosmopolitan approach debatable. Even if such governing mechanism can be employed, preservation of voices and rights of minorities and small “countries” will be continued issues just like racial and gender equality are now. But, perhaps, this attempt to justify nationality-based rights and obligations may motivate further explorations of the cosmopolitan approach and its realistic implications to present a solution to some issue we are currently facing in the world. | |
You are entitled to restrict access to your paper if you want to. But we all derive immense benefit from reading one another's work, and I hope you won't feel the need unless the subject matter is personal and its disclosure would be harmful or undesirable. |
|
CodyHuyanSecondEssay 1 - 22 Apr 2024 - Main.CodyHuyan
|
|
> > |
META TOPICPARENT | name="SecondEssay" |
It is strongly recommended that you include your outline in the body of your essay by using the outline as section titles. The headings below are there to remind you how section and subsection titles are formatted.
Justifications for Nationality Based Rights and Obligations
-- By CodyHuyan - 22 Apr 2024
Introduction
We live in a world where our rights and obligations are defined by national borders. Nationality is our form of membership in a country. With the obtainment of membership comes rights and obligations. These rights and obligations are protected by rules of law unique to each nation. U.S. nationals are obligated to pay taxes and social security used to benefit members of the community, but these benefits are not extended to individuals in other nations. What justifies these nationality-based rights and obligations? This is the question Yael Tamir identifies in the modern liberal theory.
Yael Tamir's Associative Obligation Framework and Its Inherent Dangers
Tamir suggests that liberal theory itself is not enough to provide an answer and points to national ideals hidden in the liberal agenda. In exploration for an answer, she considers the contractarian approach commonly adopted by liberal philosophers in their perspective on modern liberal societies. Yet, she soon rejects the approach as an explanation for national obligations. Criteria of state membership prioritize birthright and kinship rather than individual consent. Since “political obligations in a liberal state are not assumed in as free and rational a process as is commonly argued” (Tamir 1995, p.130), the voluntary assumption of obligations does not necessarily imply consent. Thus, the social contract theory cannot fill in the missing component in the social contract theory.
Yael Tamir suggests that the only way to justify the assumption of obligations in liberal theory is to view liberal welfare states as communities that generate associative obligations, which derive from feelings of membership, rather than contractarian entities (Tamir 1995, p.130). There is a difference in formally being a member and feeling like a member: “The fact that we are citizens of a particular state, however is a necessary but not a sufficient condition for creating obligations. […] The second statement (‘X feels that he is a member’) is the one that carries the thrust of the associative argument, suggesting that one is bound by obligations because one sees oneself as a member” (p.134-135). Although the associative approach reasonably explains the formation of the sense of community required for the voluntary assumption of mutual burdens on a philosophical approach, dangers of its realistic application cannot be ignored.
The freedom to assume and discard membership and obligation is inherently dangerous to domestic governance and the enforcement of the rule of law. Tamir would agree that obligations to a nation include obedience to rules of law that are reasonably just (p.131). Suppose a Chinese American feels alienated in the United States and chooses to pledge allegiance to China instead, despite remaining a U.S. citizen formally. Following Tamir’s associative framework, he would be released from any obligations to the U.S. based on his feelings. Such discharge from U.S. obligations justifies the alienated Chinese American to disobey American laws in areas that differ from Chinese laws. This implication endangers the rights of other members that a nation is obliged to protect, as it opens the door to exploitation of jurisdictional differences of law. Rationalization of discharge from obligations to obey laws of a country that one is still a formal member of essentially invents a new form of legal defense that cannot be proven evidentiarily but must be accepted by the court. Whenever facing a charge that may be legal in another country, the defendant can simply claim that they had assumed obligations there at the time of the offense. Neither the timing nor accuracy can be evidentiarily accountable.
Furthermore, the functioning of associative obligation framework requires accountability for the accuracy of laws of other nations, which is difficult to achieve in reality. The previous scenario of jurisdictional exploitation presumes a truthful application of another jurisdiction’s law. But what if the defendant simply chose a county of which the judge is unfamiliar with the law? Adjudication of offenses under the associative framework essentially require judges and attorneys to understand the language and laws of all countries to produce just judgments, which is an impossible ask.
An Alternative Cosmopolitan Approach
An alternative, perhaps, is to approach the question from a cosmopolitan point of view. Rather than independent entities, the world should be viewed as one exhaustive community, where birthright citizenship is nothing more than the same type of contingency that race, gender, or social class are. Nationality, then, is simply a governance mechanism to better facilitate and enforce the rights and obligations each person owes as a citizen of the world. Ultimately, irrespective of individual backgrounds and nationality, we all should be owed a common baseline of rights as human. Similar to race or religion base communities within a nation, who may hold themselves to a higher moral standard, only owe fellow citizens outside their group what the law requires; some countries may impose higher legal obligations upon their members but this does not necessarily interfere with the baseline that the world as a whole requires.
You are entitled to restrict access to your paper if you want to. But we all derive immense benefit from reading one another's work, and I hope you won't feel the need unless the subject matter is personal and its disclosure would be harmful or undesirable.
To restrict access to your paper simply delete the "#" character on the next two lines:
Note: TWiki has strict formatting rules for preference declarations. Make sure you preserve the three spaces, asterisk, and extra space at the beginning of these lines. If you wish to give access to any other users simply add them to the comma separated ALLOWTOPICVIEW list. |
|
|