|
META TOPICPARENT | name="FirstPaper" |
| |
< < | Coming to Terms with the Subjectivity of the Law | > > | Rebirth of an Ideal | | | |
< < | My Search for Understanding of Legal Opinions | > > | Law school - the reality | | | |
< < | I came to law school to be become a knowledgeable and efficient instrument of change. Not necessarily grand social change, but certainly at least individual, client-based change. I idealized the power of the law (what the law could achieve for people), but feared that I was unworthy and incapable of deciphering it. Beginning law school was extremely daunting for many reasons, but in particular because I was afraid I would not be able to follow the logic and gain a deep enough understanding of the opinions I was assigned to read. Insecurity and fear of being embarrassed in class plagued my first semester. As I tried to move past these feelings, I began to search for the logic behind opinions in the hope that it would lead me to the promise land of competence, and then further to a place where I could have meaningful insight on the material. | > > | I came to law school to be become a knowledgeable and efficient instrument of change. Not necessarily grand social change, but certainly at least individual, client-based change. I idealized the power of the law, namely, what the law could achieve for people. I believed the law could grant the concrete recognition of fundamental human rights, and the ability for every person to live with dignity and hope. But when I started law school, I quickly realized that “law school”, the institution, as well as “law”, the practice, are hyper-formal, almost scientific ways of dealing with society’s greater problems, and are not entirely focused on helping the individuals who make up society. | | | |
< < | “A Thing Is What It Does” | > > | Disconnection from the “relational” | | | |
< < | After reading and digesting Cohen, I have come to terms with an important concept: the legal system has created a network of rules, logic and terminology, which it uses to make decisions and justify those decisions, and that this process is only legitimized through itself. For Cohen this is a farce; “our legal system is filled with supernatural concepts... concepts which cannot be defined in terms of experience.” He uses the word “supernatural” to mean concepts that are unverifiable, and “experience” as concepts whose consequences are known; I would use the word subjective, meaning based on an individual's personal perspective, rather than on an independent, objective point of view, to describe this phenomena
.
But that change of words would be a change of concept, unless the
words are being used arbitrarily, outside their normal denotations.
The logic of the formalist and the factual determinations of the
consequentialist are both independent of the standpoint of the
observer, and are thus "objective" analytics. The two pairs of terms
describe different axes, and the result of conflating them can be
serious confusion.
Cohen’s point came to life for me when reading Justice Scalia’s plurality opinion in Vieth v. Jubelirer. He held that gerrymandering claims present a non-justiciable question because the Court lacks the standards to resolve these claims. Fairness, he wrote, is not “judicially manageable.” This struck me as dubious because in actuality, the Court had already made a fairness determination in deciding not to decide (rightly or wrongly irrelevant), therefore the decision seemed to be a pretense based on “supernatural concepts” of judicial manageability. In broader terms, this decision was a microcosm that revealed the subjectivity upon which the legal system forms its opinions.
But only to the extent that the Court agrees with you that its
decision about justiciability is "in actuality" a "fairness"
decision. That's not what the Court says, and I'm pretty sure it's
not what Justice Scalia believes.
I doubt I fully understand the "microcosm" idea. The Court is
making, I think you are saying, a decision which is "personal" to the
Justices doing the deciding: they think a standard of "fairness" in
drawing district lines is unmanageable, but another bunch of Justices
might feel differently. This makes clear, for you, "the subjectivity
upon which the legal system forms its opinions." So, is every
decision that a different bunch of judges might make differently a
"microcosm" of "subjective" decision? Or only such cases in which
the decision turns on judges' views of "institutional competence,"
"administrability," or "the appropriate role of the courts"? Is
"microcosm" a synonym for "example," or does it mean something more?
Increased Understanding
Cohen’s view that legal opinion is “supernatural” both furthered and complicated my understanding of the law. On one hand, I gained a deeper understanding because I was free to frame the legal issues in ways that made sense to me. It no longer seemed pedestrian to acknowledge non-doctrinal motivations behind decisions. There was no fear that I was tainting these decisions by politicizing them and thus lessening the “value” of the law in general as an impartial or pure process. On the other hand, in accepting Cohen’s viewpoint, I couldn’t help but feel a loss of the idealization I had previously felt, and I was forced to rework my sense of the “value” I thought the law provided to society.
My goals did not instantly seem to mesh with a legal system that does not say what it does; the level of subjectivity created a lack of transparency that kept the focus of the law off the people I hoped to work for and help. Subjectivity created a lack of transparency because the “supernatural concepts” behind legal opinions (transcendental nonsense) were clouding the objectives of the Court.
See, this is where the
confusion gets hopeless. Formalist ways of legal thinking, that take
the situational, personal elements out of the calculus of decision,
are now "subjective," and are "clouding" the issues, which are about
the actual people, the subjects, whose lives the decisions affect in
ways the law does not acknowledge. The complaint is that the law is
too subjective to be subjective enough. It would be better to use
Cohen's terminology, or to pick some other terms that suit you for
some other reason. Using "subjective" and "objective" in an
idiosyncratic way is not a good choice.
One example that comes to mind is Cohen’s discussion of corporations and labor unions being considered legal “persons.” To describe them as “persons” twists the natural understanding of this word in a nonsensical way that works to “thingify” the word so that these corporations and labor unions can be sued, the true objective of the Court. This lack of transparency seemed to keep the focus off the “people” because it made the law about “supernatural concepts” used to facilitate objectives rather than the tangible rights at stake in a case. This flawed system seemed insurmountable; I resigned myself to accept the law for what it was- subjective and nonsensical at times and a weak form of social control.
These again are different ideas. Law is a weak form of social
control not because it is "objective," "subjective," "formalist" or
"realist," sensible or nonsensical. Law is a weak form of social
control because the state is not the center of social cohesion: human
sociality is older than the state by eons. The forces that most
effectively tie human beings to one another, and to their social
groups, are not the written regulations of state organizations, and
the dispute-resolution processes that make use of
them.
That legal personality is not the same as biological personality
should be no surprise, and is hardly an invention of recent
constitutional law. Corporations and other collective persons are
ancient to the law, as a few moments with histories of the Roman law
will show. There's no "nonsense" in a view of legal personality
that includes artificial as well as natural persons, unless your
inclination is to ignore the large number of collectivities that
behave juridically in any society, pretending instead that there are
only individuals and the State, with nothing in between.
The Law from a Slightly More Seasoned Point of View
Cohen frames the realist search for understanding of legal reasoning as attentiveness to the consequences of legal decisions, coupled with a critical theory of values. A critical theory of values looks at human desires and habits, and through this gains “real world” (how it affects people) applicability and importance. Thus the fact that the law is far from “objective” (perfectly equitable and impartial) is not devastating to the “value” of the law in general because the “value” should not be defined in terms that are so alienated from people. People are diminished through objectivity because the focus is on the self-substantiated logic (through its own system of rules and terminology) rather than on real life consequences.
Formalism is now
"objective" again, being contrasted with the "subjective" nature of
realism. But Cohen's "ethical theory of value" is needed in order to
determine which consequences in the real world are important to
consider in setting rules and deciding disputes. The consequences
themselves are objectively measurable. Cohen doesn't think there's
no truth, only truths. He thinks that truth is determined in social
processes, which is different. (You might think of William James'
proposition that truth is "what the community of investigators is
fated to agree about, in the long run." That's science, which is
sure that it is "objective.") If anything, Cohen's "ethical theory
of value" is unconvincing as a concept, because he believes ethics
are objective: everybody's "Sunday School morality" he thinks is more
or less the same.
I interpret this as bringing the human factor into legal analysis and this gives me great hope, because I feel capable of analyzing and understanding the law from this perspective. I am also hopeful because the law’s inability to achieve perfect objectivity creates a space that allows freedom to flourish; freedom is a consequence of the law being the weakest form of social control. Within that space I hope to work.
Here it seems to me that we're closer to solid ground. The
distinction now seems to be between "formal" reasoning and "social"
or "relational" reasoning, whatever "the human factor" denotes. You
were afraid that if the law were like math or physics, or formal
propositional logic, you wouldn't be good at it. But if the law is
about interpreting and negotiating human social behavior, you could
hack it.
So indeed, you're right to be confident. Human society is not held
together by mathematics, or the rigid enforcement of inferences from
rules. It is held together by table manners, religion, sexual
possessiveness, familial love, envy, greed, persuasive rhetoric, and
fashion, among other things. Law and justice are therefore human
exercises, of which the stars and the fish are equally ignorant.
I think the route to improvement here is to worry less about Felix
Cohen: his thinking is not so much the subject as the occasion of
your thinking. Your real subject, I think, is the relief you gain
from contemplating the humanity of the law, which is more congenial
to how you think, and what you want to work with. Going beyond that
point furthers your thinking, which is what we want to do, and
presents, I think, the goal of the next revision. | > > | The goal of the first year of law school seems to be to gain a concrete understanding of legal opinions, the ability to identify the form of logic chosen in each decision, as well as to become familiar with “legal talk,” the terms and concepts that make up the bulwark of legal reasoning and concepts of justiciability. The classes and the institutional framework of the school are geared at reducing everything to generally applicable rules that seem to mimic mathematical equations and scientific truths. The result is a system based on formal reasoning, in which the importance lies in “the process”, not necessarily in the substantive and practical effects of such legal decisions. | | | |
< < | | | \ No newline at end of file | |
> > | While these fundamentals are necessary and important elements of a first year curriculum, something was lost in not encouraging any thinking or dialog about the relational or human effects of these opinions. Specifically, there was little exploration of how particular decisions affect the individuals involved in litigation, nor any analysis of how real life (outside the formal process) factors impact certain legal decisions. This lack of perspective regarding the relational factors of legal opinions manifested itself in two different and equally debilitating ways during my first year.
First, I became insecure of my ability to succeed as a law student and as a lawyer. The formal system, with its specific goal of identifying the rules of legal opinions, made me fear that I would not be able to follow the logic and gain a deep enough understanding of the opinions I was assigned to read. This insecurity became a self-fulfilling prophecy. I did not trust my instincts as a law student who could solve the “equation” and fully understand the reasoning or “legal talk” used by judges, and as a result, I did not ultimately achieve the academic success I was seeking.
Moreover, as I became obsessed with conquering the formal aspects of the law, I began to view all of the law and law school in these formal terms, and consequently lost a clear understanding of my original goal. I could no longer see how the law could make change for people because I was caught up in formal analytical exercises that reduced the legal process to identifying universal rules. I began to feel that the law was not a mechanism for helping people, but an organized way of minimizing societal troubles. This conclusion was not only enforced by the work done in the classroom but by the institutional focus of law school in general. The focus has not been on creating “lawyers as advocates,” but more so lawyers as “academics,” “profit-maximizers” or “people in power.” The path for achieving my original goal began to fade; it seemed far-fetched and misguided.
Goal back into focus
Detached from my original reason for going to law school, I geared up for the completion of an institutional requirement – summer internship. Though mentally exhausted, I started my summer internship soon after the end of finals. I went to work for Catholic Charities Immigration and Refugee Services. Because the organization is a non-profit, I was given instant responsibility; entire asylum cases were put into my hands, as well as all client interaction. It was finally the relational experience I had been seeking. It provided a tangible application of how the law can actually help people, and it revived and refocused my goal. I was able to use the formal legal principles and processes, so stressed in 1L, to achieve a real-life result: protecting someone from horrific persecution and possible torture.
Meditating on this revival, I feel that this internship saved the law for me and put the experience of law school into perspective. I now see the role of formal study and how the law can be practically used to achieve human, relational goals. The relief this provided me was immense, for it allowed me to get my head above water and regain the most important element to success in any career path: my confidence.
Word count: 784 |
|