MichaelDignanThirdPaper 3 - 26 Aug 2009 - Main.MichaelDignan
|
|
META TOPICPARENT | name="ThirdPaper" |
-- MichaelDignan - 03 Jun 2009 | | the political operators Ralph Reed and Karl Rove. "Judicial
restraint" has a different and less low-rent political history.
But that's a different story.
\ No newline at end of file | |
> > | * I see that the argument doesn't really relate to the conclusion. I didn't mean to say that decisions expanding civil rights have never been called "activist." I meant to say that those decisions are not commonly associated with the label as used by pundits today in denunciations of current judges and decisions about abortion, gun control, and affirmative action. They typically don't associate decisions like Brown with the term "activism" because it is politically expedient to be pro- Brown, and so associating those landmark civil rights cases with activism would hamper their campaign to demonize the term.
The point I was trying to make was that "activism", as it is currently flung around by the media has less to do with actual judicial activism than politics. And that if the media were being fair, it would recognize that both sides of the political line have been activist about certain issues. Therefore, if "activism" was being used fairly, it wouldn't be a helpful term because it would describe both sides. I don't think the term is necessarily vacuous, although you imply that you might think so. It is simply non-discriminating because most judges issue activist decisions on some issues. If that doesn't make sense then the whole paper should be scrapped. |
|
MichaelDignanThirdPaper 2 - 23 Aug 2009 - Main.EbenMoglen
|
|
META TOPICPARENT | name="ThirdPaper" |
-- MichaelDignan - 03 Jun 2009 | | In United States v. Miller, the court refused to strike down the National Firearms Act, which prohibited transporting sawed-off shotguns in interstate commerce, despite a challenge that it violated a Second Amendment right to keep and bear arms: | |
< < | In the absence of any evidence tending to show that possession or use of a "shotgun having a barrel of less than eighteen inches in length" at this time has some reasonable relationship to the preservation or efficiency of a well regulated militia, we cannot say that the Second Amendment guarantees the right to keep and bear such an instrument. 307 U.S. 174 (1939). | > > | In the absence of any evidence tending to show that possession or use of a "shotgun having a barrel of less than eighteen inches in length" at this time has some reasonable relationship to the preservation or efficiency of a well regulated militia, we cannot say that the Second Amendment guarantees the right to keep and bear such an instrument. 307 U.S. 174 (1939). | | The test then seemed to be whether or not the regulation of firearms had a reasonable relationship to maintaining a well regulated militia. There existed no broad right to ownership of firearms, free from state or national regulation. | |
< < | In two earlier cases from the 19th century the court also rejected broad interpretations of the Second Amendment. In United States v. Cruikshank, the court found that “bearing arms for a lawful purpose” was not a right protected by the Constitution. 92 U.S. 542, 551 (1876). Its construal of the right protected by the Second Amendment was based on the presumption that the amendment was enacted to empower state and local militias to prevent dominance by a federal standing army. The court, therefore, found that any right protected by the Second Amendment was protected from infringement by the federal government only. It declined to elaborate on the boundaries of the right itself. In Presser v. Illinois, the court upheld a law that prohibited unauthorized associations from training and drilling together as military organizations. 116 U.S. 252 (1886). It once again interpreted the right protected by the Second Amendment within the context of militia service, mentioning that: | > > | In two earlier cases from the 19th century the court also rejected broad interpretations of the Second Amendment. In United States v. Cruikshank, the court found that “bearing arms for a lawful purpose” was not a right protected by the Constitution. 92 U.S. 542, 551 (1876). Its construal of the right protected by the Second Amendment was based on the presumption that the amendment was enacted to empower state and local militias to prevent dominance by a federal standing army. The court, therefore, found that any right protected by the Second Amendment was protected from infringement by the federal government only. It declined to elaborate on the boundaries of the right itself. In Presser v. Illinois, the court upheld a law that prohibited unauthorized associations from training and drilling together as military organizations. 116 U.S. 252 (1886). It once again interpreted the right protected by the Second Amendment within the context of militia service, mentioning that: | | | |
< < | It is undoubtedly true that all citizens capable of bearing arms constitute the reserved military force or reserve militia of the United States as well as of the states, and, in view of this prerogative of the general government, as well as of its general powers, the states cannot, even laying the constitutional provision in question out of view, prohibit the people from keeping and bearing arms, so as to deprive the United States of their rightful resource for maintaining the public security, and disable the people from performing their duty to the general government. Presser at 266. | > > | It is undoubtedly true that all citizens capable of bearing arms constitute the reserved military force or reserve militia of the United States as well as of the states, and, in view of this prerogative of the general government, as well as of its general powers, the states cannot, even laying the constitutional provision in question out of view, prohibit the people from keeping and bearing arms, so as to deprive the United States of their rightful resource for maintaining the public security, and disable the people from performing their duty to the general government. Presser at 266. | | It both cases, the ability of the state to regulate firearms is not restricted by the Second Amendment. Neither case purports to create a general, individual right to keep and bear arms. The legislature also seems to have adopted that understanding, enacting laws in 1927 and 1934 regulating delivery and possession of certain firearms. | | The language of the Second Amendment itself does not plainly create a broad right to private gun ownership. The Second Amendment reads: | |
< < | A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed. | > > | A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed. | | When considering the scope of the right guaranteed by the amendment, it seems critical to first consider its purpose. While Justice Scalia prefers to jump straight to the operative clause, ignoring the preamble, that does not seem to be the natural way of interpreting a text. As Justice Stevens asserts, the preamble identifies the preservation of the militia as the Amendment’s purpose, because it is necessary to guard against the tyranny of a strong federal government. Having recognized its purpose, Stevens narrowly and reasonably interprets the right not to include a right to private ownership of handguns, consistent with past precedent. Scalia, on the other hand, starts with the assumption of a right to possess handguns, and then interprets the prefatory clause and previous case law to not contradict a broader right. His opinion is a clear example of activism. | | IV. Activism is not a useful label
Seeing that the issue is not as clear cut as the majority would like it to be, judicial restraint seems to dictate that the court should interpret the right narrowly. Scalia and the majority, however, intent on expanding the right to gun ownership, struck down a law enacted by the D.C. legislature, banning some, but not all, firearms. While conservatives on the right will castigate liberal judges for being too activist, they embrace the kind of conservative activism seen in Heller. There is also little rancor over civil rights decisions that protected the equality of minorities and women under the Constitution, despite the fact that they must be classified as activist decisions. Rather than use the loaded and confusing term, activist, it would be better to speak clearly and descriptively about the political propensities of judges. Commentators that describe potential court nominees as too activist only do a disservice to the public by casting aspersion on a term that can be applied to both sides, as well as some of the most illustrious decisions in United States history. | |
> > |
- This draft's structure of argument doesn't make sense to me. You begin by saying that "judicial activism" is an epithet used to criticise the work of liberal judges, but not, for example, the decisions of conservative justices in general, and in a Second Amendment case in particular. You then take a great deal of space to show that there are other plausible outcomes in Miller, and that upholding the statute might well have been more in keeping with the scant existing precedent in the area than the recognition of an individual right good against prohibitory state and local regulation. You then assert that "activism is not a use label" at all, which seems absolutely obvious and yet completely unentailed by all the preceding argument, as well as inconsistent with what was said at the beginning, in which the problem wasn't the vacuity of the epithet but the inconsistency of its application.
- I don't know where you get the evidence to support the claim that decisions expanding civil rights have not been called "activist." As an epithet, "judicial activism" began its career in the "massive resistance" to Brown. Like "states' rights" and "strict construction," it has always been political code for "I am with you in supporting white supremacy." Its association with other anti-liberal causes results from the synthesis in the modern so-called "conservative" electoral coalition of traditional authoritarians, Protestant evangelicals, libertarians, anti-abortion Catholics and Orthodox Jews, low-tax class warriors and white supremacy. "Judicial activism" jumps from the white supremacist rhetoric to the anti-abortion coalition in the lingo of Orrin Hatch and Jesse Helms. It gets picked up by Falwell and Dobson and Perkins and Wildmon through the political operators Ralph Reed and Karl Rove. "Judicial restraint" has a different and less low-rent political history. But that's a different story.
| | \ No newline at end of file |
|
MichaelDignanThirdPaper 1 - 03 Jun 2009 - Main.MichaelDignan
|
|
> > |
META TOPICPARENT | name="ThirdPaper" |
-- MichaelDignan - 03 Jun 2009
"Activism" and the Second Amendment
I. The problem of “activism”
“Activist” is a word often used to denote a “liberal” judge. It is associated with expanding constitutional rights and broadly expanding governmental obligations revolving around protection of those rights. While applied with gusto to describe liberal judges who favor abortion rights and affirmative action, it is often neglected when considering landmark cases involving desegregation and expansion of women’s rights. Whether or not the label has value to begin with, its use as a synonym for (and denunciation of) liberal judges is clearly problematic when considering Second Amendment rights.
II. History of second amendment rights from previous cases
The majority opinion in District of Columbia v. Heller should not be considered anything but activist, despite being written by the conservative originalist, Antonin Scalia. 554 U.S. _ (2008). The Supreme Court never previously recognized a right as broad as the one Scalia identifies.
In United States v. Miller, the court refused to strike down the National Firearms Act, which prohibited transporting sawed-off shotguns in interstate commerce, despite a challenge that it violated a Second Amendment right to keep and bear arms:
In the absence of any evidence tending to show that possession or use of a "shotgun having a barrel of less than eighteen inches in length" at this time has some reasonable relationship to the preservation or efficiency of a well regulated militia, we cannot say that the Second Amendment guarantees the right to keep and bear such an instrument. 307 U.S. 174 (1939).
The test then seemed to be whether or not the regulation of firearms had a reasonable relationship to maintaining a well regulated militia. There existed no broad right to ownership of firearms, free from state or national regulation.
In two earlier cases from the 19th century the court also rejected broad interpretations of the Second Amendment. In United States v. Cruikshank, the court found that “bearing arms for a lawful purpose” was not a right protected by the Constitution. 92 U.S. 542, 551 (1876). Its construal of the right protected by the Second Amendment was based on the presumption that the amendment was enacted to empower state and local militias to prevent dominance by a federal standing army. The court, therefore, found that any right protected by the Second Amendment was protected from infringement by the federal government only. It declined to elaborate on the boundaries of the right itself. In Presser v. Illinois, the court upheld a law that prohibited unauthorized associations from training and drilling together as military organizations. 116 U.S. 252 (1886). It once again interpreted the right protected by the Second Amendment within the context of militia service, mentioning that:
It is undoubtedly true that all citizens capable of bearing arms constitute the reserved military force or reserve militia of the United States as well as of the states, and, in view of this prerogative of the general government, as well as of its general powers, the states cannot, even laying the constitutional provision in question out of view, prohibit the people from keeping and bearing arms, so as to deprive the United States of their rightful resource for maintaining the public security, and disable the people from performing their duty to the general government. Presser at 266.
It both cases, the ability of the state to regulate firearms is not restricted by the Second Amendment. Neither case purports to create a general, individual right to keep and bear arms. The legislature also seems to have adopted that understanding, enacting laws in 1927 and 1934 regulating delivery and possession of certain firearms.
III. Interpreting the language itself
The language of the Second Amendment itself does not plainly create a broad right to private gun ownership. The Second Amendment reads:
A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a free State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed.
When considering the scope of the right guaranteed by the amendment, it seems critical to first consider its purpose. While Justice Scalia prefers to jump straight to the operative clause, ignoring the preamble, that does not seem to be the natural way of interpreting a text. As Justice Stevens asserts, the preamble identifies the preservation of the militia as the Amendment’s purpose, because it is necessary to guard against the tyranny of a strong federal government. Having recognized its purpose, Stevens narrowly and reasonably interprets the right not to include a right to private ownership of handguns, consistent with past precedent. Scalia, on the other hand, starts with the assumption of a right to possess handguns, and then interprets the prefatory clause and previous case law to not contradict a broader right. His opinion is a clear example of activism.
Scalia’s interpretation is troubling for its attempt to reconcile constitutional forms of gun regulation, such as a ban on automatic weapons or sawed-off shotguns, with the new right to own handguns. It is difficult to make a convincing case that a handgun ban is unconstitutional simply because many Americans own them for self-defense purposes. Since he has not offered a convincing basis for judging the constitutionality of potential regulations, the decision seems as arbitrary as the supposedly constitutional restrictions on automatic weapons. The dissent’s opinions at least have a foundation from which to base a constitutional inquiry into a provision.
IV. Activism is not a useful label
Seeing that the issue is not as clear cut as the majority would like it to be, judicial restraint seems to dictate that the court should interpret the right narrowly. Scalia and the majority, however, intent on expanding the right to gun ownership, struck down a law enacted by the D.C. legislature, banning some, but not all, firearms. While conservatives on the right will castigate liberal judges for being too activist, they embrace the kind of conservative activism seen in Heller. There is also little rancor over civil rights decisions that protected the equality of minorities and women under the Constitution, despite the fact that they must be classified as activist decisions. Rather than use the loaded and confusing term, activist, it would be better to speak clearly and descriptively about the political propensities of judges. Commentators that describe potential court nominees as too activist only do a disservice to the public by casting aspersion on a term that can be applied to both sides, as well as some of the most illustrious decisions in United States history. |
|
|