|
META TOPICPARENT | name="FirstPaper" |
| |
< < | Federalism as a Pretext | > > | A Healthy Distrust | | -- By PrashantRai - 16 Feb 2012 | |
< < | In “The Path of the Law” by Oliver Wendell Holmes, Holmes argues that the goal of a practitioner of the law is to predict outcomes. The reason is that lawyers argue before the court not for the pursuit of a more perfect system of rules, but because they serve clients who want the best possible outcome in terms of their own personal interest. This creates an incentive for lawyers to choose what arguments to make not based on what they truly think the relevant values in play are, but rather based on predictions about how they think the court will rule. That is, a predictive model for argument selection will by its very nature serve the interests of the client better than a normative model based on the lawyer’s assessment of what the doctrine should be because, in many cases, the normative model will suggest arguments that have a lower chance of winning the day because of their incompatibility with the judge’s beliefs. | > > | What does it mean when we say that a court acted justly? On one view, a judge rules in accordance with justice only when, instead of letting her political biases control the outcome of her ruling, she reasons from principle. The just judge, so the argument goes, does not have an outcome in mind when she begins her reasoned path towards a ruling. The fact that one possible outcome is inconsistent with her personal political beliefs does not count against that outcome, for the just judge’s first principle is that her role is merely to enforce the law. Results-oriented judicial reasoning, on the other hand, is, on this view, the antithesis of Justice. Any hint that one’s personal beliefs about what “should” be the outcome of the trial influence one’s decision-making evokes criticisms that one is “legislating from the bench,” which serves as incontrovertible evidence of one’s incompetence. | | | |
< < | That's not what Holmes
says. It's a bunch of inferences piled on one another and the result
may be your view, but it has nothing to do with
his.
Unfortunately, following a predictive model leads lawyers to choose the path of least resistance. This prevents positive change in the law and reinforces status quo doctrine.
Why? Whether I am
working for a client who needs a change in the law or can make the
existing legal situation beneficial to him is immaterial to the need
both clients will have to predict the reception of particular
arguments or the legal effect of particular transactions. The effort
to forecast outcomes is part of risk management whether one's client
is going to choose the path of least resistance or not. As a lawyer,
I am not, in general, a party representing conservative or "path of
least resistance" interests. But that does not change the fact that
I recognize what I do as well described in Holmes'
terms.
Additionally, a predictive model will often encourage lawyers to appeal to ideological commitments of the judge.
Why? Most of the time,
prediction of what the courts will do in fact has nothing to do with
any particular judge. In counseling a client before there is
litigation, how could the possible views of any particular judge play
the slightest role in the forecasts made by the counselor?
The reason is that judges do not rule entirely, if at all, based on logic or ethics. Rather, while judges couch their decisions in the language of reason, there is always a lurking dogma that remains unspoken. There is no view from nowhere; while a judge may claim that his decision flows from a perfect deduction, there is always a missing premise – a belief that lacks rational justification. Says Holmes,
“But certainty generally is illusion, and repose is not the destiny of man. Behind the logical form lies a judgment as to the relative worth and importance of competing legislative grounds, often an inarticulate and unconscious judgment, it is true, and yet the very root and nerve of the whole proceeding.” Holmes, “The Path of the Law”
An irrelevant use of the
quotation, so far as I can see. Connect it up or let it
drop.
The most obvious example of this is when courts appeal to the values of federalism in justifying decisions that are difficult to classify as anything other than ideological. Federalism as a pretext for the advancement of dogma is best seen in a series of three Supreme Court cases from the last 20 years. In 1995, in US v. Lopez, the Supreme Court ruled that the Gun-Free School Zones Act of 1990 was unconstitutional because it was not within Congress’ commerce power. The justification provided was that a ban on guns in school zones does not substantially affect interstate commerce. The fear was that if the court ruled that such a ban was within Congress’ commerce power, then the commerce power “lacks any real limits because, depending on the level of generality, any activity can be looked upon as commercial.” Then, in 2000, in US v. Morrison, the Supreme Court found that the civil remedy provision of the Violence Against Women Act was unconstitutional because “gender-motivated crimes of violence are not [economic] activity […] Thus far in our Nation’s history our cases have upheld Commerce Clause regulation of intrastate activity only where that activity is economic in nature.” Chief Justice Rehnquist penned both decisions, which is ironic given that in Morrison the court adopted a fundamentally different test for evaluating a statute in light of the commerce power than that of Lopez. The court constructed the Lopez test, a pragmatic test of effects, as a response to the inadequacy of formalist distinctions between essentially “economic” and “noneconomic” activity in protecting a balance between federal and state powers. Yet, not five years later the same Chief Justice wrote that evaluating a statute in terms of its effects risks the destruction of federalism. Justice Breyer notes in his dissent in Morrison that the Chief Justice’s appeal to formalist distinctions disconnects federalism from its functional purposes. This kind of transcendental nonsense, as noted by Felix Cohen, is ever-present in American jurisprudence, and separates judicial opinion from the pragmatic impact that decisions have on our lives.
A long, complex paragraph that does nothing whatever to advance your argument.
The coup de grace, however, came in 2005 when in Gonzalez v. Raich the Supreme Court found that the Controlled Substances Act is a valid exercise of federal power because intrastate medicinal marijuana distribution in California substantially affects interstate commerce. Gone were the fears of an all-powerful federal government overreaching into pockets of regulation traditionally carved out as distinctly state governed. The majority opinion stressed the importance of the Supremacy Clause; the risk of an imbalance between federal and state powers was conspicuously absent from the discussion. Note also that the court again flip flops back to the substantial affects test from Lopez and ignores the above quoted language from Morrison. Nevertheless, what is common among the three cases is that in Morrison and Lopez, the court struck down legislation backed by Democrats in Congress, and then in Gonzalez, in what seemed like a case for a straightforward application of the doctrine established by Morrison and Lopez, the court upholds legislation advanced by President “I am not a crook” Nixon.
The upshot is that federalism matters when progressive legislation is under scrutiny, but is of secondary concern to the Supremacy Clause when conservative policy is in play. Frank Cross argues in “Realism about Federalism” that these and similar decisions use federalism concerns “as mere stalking horses for an anti-regulatory ideological agenda.”
Maybe. If so it's an
example of a kind of post-hoc rationalization that is only possible
for courts of last resort in judicial review situations, where the
fate of a statute, rather than a series of individual liability
decisions, is at stake. This is a beyond-negligible part of the
legal system overall, and would hardly constitute a sound basis for
reaching general conclusions in a theory of
adjudication.
The broader point, however, is that judicial opinions are often backwards reasoning in the sense that the court picks the outcome it wants and then produces a rationalization to make it look as though the court reasoned to its conclusion instead of from it. Holmes concludes,
“Judges themselves have failed adequately to recognize their duty of weighing considerations of social advantage. The duty is inevitable, and the result of the often proclaimed judicial aversion to deal with such considerations is simply to leave the very ground and foundation of judgments inarticulate, and often unconscious.”
I don't know what the
real point is to this draft. The long, clotted middle grafs on recent
Supreme Court Commerce Clause cases do not seem to me very
interesting, but the title suggests that they're what you consider
important. What if anything have you contributed to the flood of
mediocre literature on the partisanship of the contemporary Court?
On the other hand, the Holmesian grafs on either side of this
indigestible lump do not, to my mind, fairly convey Holmes' point,
and don't seem to me to have anything directly to do with whatever
issue it is that makes these cases important, except insofar as
Holmes offers an early version of the basic realist proposition that
judicial opinions are rationalizations. If this is true, it is not
true merely in contexts full of evidently political constitutional
rhetoric but also in cases raising quotidian issues and resolving
them tidily. Proving that constitutional law is politics under
another name is trivial for the realist. Is that actually the theme
of the draft? | > > | This is of course an unattainable ideal, as the character Celia Day notes in Lawrence Joseph’s “All Great Problems Come from the Streets.” When asked if interpreting the law involves personal and even political judgments, the fictional Federal Judge responds, “Of course it does. So what? You control it, that’s all. Our commission is to keep our personal predispositions under control.” So, in reality, a just judge does not entirely avoid inserting one’s personal beliefs into one’s decision-making, since this is impossible. Justice Holmes notes,” Behind the logical form lies a judgment as to the relative worth and importance of competing legislative grounds, often an inarticulate and unconscious judgment, it is true, and yet the very root and nerve of the whole proceeding.” It is a ruse, therefore, to think that judges render decisions without at least unstated reference to their own psychological attitudes towards the facts of a case and their preferred outcome. | | | |
< < | | > > | Judge Day’s solution is for judges to acknowledge that subjective attitudes inform one’s decisions, but to limit their influence as best as one can. Day suggests that the reason why judges keep their personal beliefs under control is “by force of [their] commission.” It seems that what Day means is that judges feel an obligation to reason from principle rather than from opinion because they have been entrusted with the responsibility to do so. But this kind of check is purely intra-psychic in that it depends on the judge having an antecedent belief that divorcing their decision-making from their personal beliefs is something that they should do. Without a doubt there are many judges that self-check quite effectively. But what is clear to me and what anyone can discern from a perusal of recent Supreme Court opinions is that there are also many judges that do not, which is of special concern when what is it stake is freedom from incarceration or other fundamental rights.
This places me, and any other person who fears for their rights when the only check against the power of judges to define (and as a corollary, to limit) what our rights are, at a crossroads. One option is to assuage one’s fears with reassurances that the structure of the United States government is such that the rights of American citizens are not subject to the personal whims of judges that are appointed by partisan politicians (“federalism,” “checks and balances,” “separation of powers,” “the appeals process”). This approach, however, is really just an exercise in cognitive dissonance in the sense that it might placate our fear but is inconsistent with what we know to be the case; additionally, such an approach only serves to re-entrench the control the state apparatus has over us by assigning to it our blind faith in the way that a child trusts her parents to not hurt her.
The other option is to develop protections -- for oneself and for those who cannot protect themselves -- that are independent of the state. This, in my mind, is the role of the lawyer, and is why I attend law school. Such a solution harkens to the Gandhian idea that “Swaraj” (self-rule) requires “Swadeshi” (self-reliance). This applies both on a macro scale, such that populations should not depend on the protection of a sovereign against oppression from that same sovereign, but also on a personal level in terms of the relation between an individual and the arbiters of her fate. I refuse to passively rest my freedom from statist violence on the shoulders of judges. Instead, I choose to arm myself with the law. This is I think at least partially what Eben means when he says that what we gain from law school is not a job, but a license. The ability to practice law represents a power much larger than that of fiscal stability. It represents both a shield and a sword against oppression and violence.
It is in this sense that I will never be without clients, for my first and primary client is myself. However, not everyone has the privilege of attending law school, let alone one such as our own. This puts us in a position of special responsibility towards those that do not have the tools to protect themselves from the monopoly on violence possessed by the state, and as a result, its judges. Gandhi made clear that on his view, mutual assistance is essential to self-reliance. Sacrificing one’s license at the altar of capitalism is therefore not just self-mutilation but a loss for the community of people that would otherwise gain from your protection. | | |
|