|
META TOPICPARENT | name="FirstEssay" |
| | Building the Bio-Data Commons | |
< < | In simple terms, a commons is a resource accessible to all members of society. While commons are most often associated with collective ownership, the concept does not preclude private ownership that is then shared freely. Historical commons often required contribution from all potential beneficiaries, whereas knowledge commons participation is voluntary. In the context of bio-data, contribution is involuntary once an individual uses a biofeedpack product, but the choice to use one is voluntary. Furthermore, ownership depends on one's temporal perspective. Prior to using a biofeedback product, any individual "owns" his or her bio-data. Once a user, the company that operates the product "owns" the bio-data. The use of the biofeedback product can thus be construed either as a contribution by an individual of his or her data to the common pool managed by the product's company, or as the involuntary privatization of a good. The view one chooses between these two alternatives largely depends on the company's later use of the data. If the data is used for the benefit of the public at large, the transaction will likely be viewed as a contribution to the commons, or at worst expropriation in the public interest, but if it is used for the benefit of the product's company, the transaction will look more like stealing. | > > | In simple terms, a commons is a resource accessible to all members of society. While commons are most often associated with collective ownership, the concept does not preclude private ownership that is then shared freely. Historical commons often required contribution from all potential beneficiaries, whereas knowledge commons participation is voluntary. In the context of bio-data, contribution is involuntary once an individual uses a biofeedpack product, but the choice to use one is voluntary. Furthermore, ownership depends on one's temporal perspective. Prior to using a biofeedback product, any individual "owns" his or her bio-data.
The quotation marks
actually means she doesn't own, because it isn't property. You
might want to take that into account. This is also why the cultural
commons, which are directly interwoven with a statutory monopoly
scheme creating property where none would otherwise exist are
distinct from this situation.
Once a user, the company that operates the product "owns" the bio-data.
Here the quote marks mean, no they don't, but there are some
contractual provisions somewhere that determine the relative rights
of the two parties in the event of particular occurrences. That's
not the same thing, and doesn't necessarily lead to the same
conclusions, particularly with respect to third parties, including
regulators.
The use of the biofeedback product can thus be construed either as a contribution by an individual of his or her data to the common pool managed by the product's company, or as the involuntary privatization of a good. The view one chooses between these two alternatives largely depends on the company's later use of the data. If the data is used for the benefit of the public at large, the transaction will likely be viewed as a contribution to the commons, or at worst expropriation in the public interest, but if it is used for the benefit of the product's company, the transaction will look more like stealing. | | As it stands, bio-data is on the cusp of becoming a commons, and equally at risk of being completely private. Data collection has reached the first stage of commons creation, the collection of a private good into a collective pool, but has yet to complete the second stage, the use of that pool. Like historical commons, which often mandated contribution or restricted private ownership of a certain type of good, bio-data requires contribution by all users of biofeedback products and restricts private ownership by refusing to offer users a collection opt-out right. The knowledge commons model is different, in that it is generated through the voluntary participation of users who post or edit content or publish information publicly. However, like the knowledge commons, data collection can be used by the broader public. While traditional commons only directly served the community that participated in them (although they served the broader public insofar as they protected natural resources from privatization and consumption, for example), the knowledge commons is provided for the benefit of any individual, regardless of his or her contribution. Similarly, bio-data can be used by and for the benefit of the public at large, not just by users of the products that perform the collection. | | Ultimately, just as the knowledge commons' governance efforts stem from an understanding of commons governance generally, regulation of bio-data should reflect the aim of making bio-data a commons that serves the public interest. An initial step is to require biofeedback products to follow one of two mandated models. The first, the commons model, restricts unconsented sale to or access by third parties of any data and requires collaboration with research scientists to use the information for the public good. The second, the private good model, requires a collection opt-out for product users. If a company reserves the right to use collected data for its own gain, users must also retain the right to use the product for their own benefit, without the collection of that data in the common pool. | |
< < |
| > > |
An "understanding of common governance generally" might be too
general, for the reasons provided above. Nor is it clear what you
believe are the differences between "anonymous" and aggregate data,
or why contract provisions that are obviously subject to an infinite
number of public regulatory interventions should be treated as
property or "property." You're right that one possible outcome of
all this analysis would be a consumer right to the "small data,"
concerning only his- or herself. Another way of looking at that is
that there's a design flaw in the machines, which could be rectified
by changing their software. But the "anonymous" (actually just
badly pseudo-anonymized) or aggregate data is another question. You
might ask it slightly more generally, by asking about public health
data in general. And then, if you want to be bold about it, you can
ask yourself whether people could be required to produce such data
for aggregation, if not, why not, and where that leads you.
| | | |
< < | |
|