|
META TOPICPARENT | name="WebPreferences" |
| |
< < | Ready for review, comments, etc. | | Selling Your Soul (Part 2): The Attention Economy | | A Paradox | |
< < | A particularly troubling paradox is brought into play by the rise of the attention economy that challenges our traditional boundaries of property. A traditional property right typically is recognized by society when it is necessary to combat the tragedy of the commons. However, whereas the value of traditional property is held in its exclusivity, this concept is reversed for attention value since more attention is only generated by allowing access to as many eyeballs as we can attract. Any restrictions in distribution necessarily decreases the number of eyeballs paying attention to our thing, and thus its value. Even more importantly, when the medium of money is replaced with the medium of attention for the determination of wealth, the dangers of over-commodification become uncontrollable. While much of the focus of this paradox has been directed at the fate of intellectual property in the attention economy, there is no reason that the end game will not affect all property types. This paper will focus on the problem of commodification. | > > | A particularly troubling paradox is brought into play by the rise of the attention economy that challenges our traditional boundaries of property. A traditional property right typically is recognized by society when it is necessary to combat the tragedy of the commons.
This is a good example of the most serious
conceptualist error. The sentence above is abstract theory claiming
to be history. Now instead of a definition assumed for the purposes
of a philosophic argument abstracted from reality, or a piece of
economic theory about where property rights should be created or are
likely to be observed, you've made a statement ostensibly about what
has actually been happening in human societies over the past 9,000
years or so. Oddly enough, this summary of what has happened, which
was not actually based on any historical investigation, is completely
wrong. Among other things, it leaves out the rule of power seeking
or to increase inequality through class conflict, where the creation of
property is the tragedy of the commons, and deliberate murder is
the kind of tragedy it is. This motif is common enough in
"traditional property right" creation that more practically-oriented
theorists, like Marx, have considered it the center of the whole
show.
However, whereas the value of traditional property is held in its exclusivity, this concept is reversed for attention value since more attention is only generated by allowing access to as many eyeballs as we can attract. Any restrictions in distribution necessarily decreases the number of eyeballs paying attention to our thing, and thus its value.
This statement is not even theoretically correct. A
moment's abstract logical consideration will show that many
conceivable restrictions on distribution will have no such effect,
because distribution has already saturated the relevant attention
market, given linguistic, cultural or other background limits on who
will be interested, etc.
Even more importantly, when the medium of money is replaced with the medium of attention for the determination of wealth,
A process which does not occur because celebrity
attracts money, right?
the dangers of over-commodification become uncontrollable. While much of the focus of this paradox has been directed at the fate of intellectual property in the attention economy, there is no reason that the end game will not affect all property types. This paper will focus on the problem of commodification. | |
The Problem of Markets | | Perhaps the biggest problem inherent in any type of market, and described by Marx, is that it knows no ethical boundaries; if left unregulated, it will eventually envelope all aspects of human wants. Particularly notorious are the issues of (wage) slavery and the sex trade. Inherent in the criticism is a sense that certain things should not be economic commodities, but rather remain purely aspects of our individual or shared autonomy. To allow it to be traded for value/wealth is to devalue both our personal and collective autonomy, and shapes a world ripe for abuse of the lower class. In response to these concerns with the dangers of commodification, society has developed an array of laws prohibiting or restricting our negative freedom in certain aspects of our autonomy deemed to be essentially (and prescriptively) non-economic. Slavery is prohibited altogether, although wage slavery is still allowed subject to heavy social regulations. Sex is prohibited to be directly sold for money (wealth), but may still be bartered for in gold-digging, and obviously can be gifted. All of these are resistances to an rampant and inevitable natural commodification of all things in a capitalistic society. | |
> > | It's not clear whether you are trying to follow a
line of argument or making it up as you go along here. Once again,
the idea of legal and ethical norms as cultural limitations on the
market that respond to commodification is conceptualism pretending to
be history: the cultural environment antedates the cash nexus, as
Marx is insistent on pointing out. | | The Problem of Market Control | |
< < | These controls our society exerts on the natural market are only possible because money is a tangible, direct, and easily observable transaction. While trading sex for fancy dinners and fine jewelery is not substantively different from trading sex for the wealth (money) used to buy those things, our ability to differentiate it from an approved relationship is much higher. After the transition into the attention economy when wealth shifts from tangible money to the amorphous attention standard, it will become impossible to enforce most of the controls against commodification we currently have. We cannot regulated sex for attention-wealth because the identity of sex necessitates attention. We can no longer enforce labor laws when the adequacy of the compensation becomes the amount/quality of attention the worker receives for the work. Thus, in the new attention economy, we will necessarily be able to buy, trade, and give up anything we physically can outside of reliance on positive government enforcement, at the complete mercy of the structural implications of the new world. This new economy leaves government with only one blunt tool to work with: Complete prohibition. Shade of gray will be but a thing in the past, an impossible distinction in the future. | > > | These controls our society exerts on the natural market are only possible because money is a tangible, direct, and easily observable transaction. While trading sex for fancy dinners and fine jewelery is not substantively different from trading sex for the wealth (money) used to buy those things, our ability to differentiate it from an approved relationship is much higher.
This is nonsense. Your inexperience of the
diversity of real relationships real people have is showing. Your
supposed norm against selling sex doesn't exist. No one can and no
one does prosecute commercial sex except where operating on a
short-term transactional basis not under the protection of corrupt
police. Once the transaction leaves the street, the trick hotel or
the outcall service and becomes a continuing arrangement, the law
necessarily ceases to concern itself with anything other than whether
all parties pay taxes.
After the transition into the attention economy when wealth shifts from tangible money to the amorphous attention standard, it will become impossible to enforce most of the controls against commodification we currently have. We cannot regulated sex for attention-wealth because the identity of sex necessitates attention.
This doesn't make any sense to me.
We can no longer enforce labor laws when the adequacy of the compensation becomes the amount/quality of attention the worker receives for the work.
This doesn't ever happen. You've taken an aspect of
the zero-marginal-cost economy and hypothesized its transition to the
economy of non-zero marginal cost without
thinking.
Thus, in the new attention economy, we will necessarily be able to buy, trade, and give up anything we physically can outside of reliance on positive government enforcement, at the complete mercy of the structural implications of the new world. This new economy leaves government with only one blunt tool to work with: Complete prohibition. Shade of gray will be but a thing in the past, an impossible distinction in the future.
This is an absurd conclusion from impossible
premises. | |
An Identity Crisis
| |
< < | At its core, the problems illustrated here is an issue of identity. Money is an extrinsic factor in any transaction; it is always to trade money for X (two separate matters linked by the transaction), and never that to do/use/perform X money is necessary (one single matter which constitutes the entire transaction). Without severability, what we have is not a transaction between two things, but the performance of one. Regulating the attention received by a piano performance is nonsensical, because the purpose of the piano performance is the audience. On the other hand, regulating ticket sales in terms of number of dollars is a rather simple task for any government. Although the attention-economy transaction is still in a quid pro quo framework (performance for attention), the commodity attention given was physically necessary for the reception of the concert. Similarly, while we can currently regulate prostitution without prohibiting all sex, since the reception of sex necessitates attention, our tool for differentiating commodified sex with non-commodified sex will cease to exist. In an attention economy there will be no more difference between selling and giving. Thus, everything that is sold will have been given and everything given freely sold. In fact, it can be said that all things will necessarily be commodified, and all people (eyeballs) necessarily become commodities; for what else are we but our consciousness? | > > | At its core, the problems illustrated here is an issue of identity. Money is an extrinsic factor in any transaction; it is always to trade money for X (two separate matters linked by the transaction), and never that to do/use/perform X money is necessary (one single matter which constitutes the entire transaction).
No, because not all money is fungible. The payment
of a traveler's check for an antique Roman gold solidus comes to
mind. "Never" was wrong. In general, money is a medium of exchange.
Having said which, you can skip all the rest.
Without severability, what we have is not a transaction between two things, but the performance of one. Regulating the attention received by a piano performance is nonsensical, because the purpose of the piano performance is the audience. On the other hand, regulating ticket sales in terms of number of dollars is a rather simple task for any government. Although the attention-economy transaction is still in a quid pro quo framework (performance for attention), the commodity attention given was physically necessary for the reception of the concert.
You fooled yourself with that argument because you
used a "concert" with "seats" in the non-zero marginal cost world. If you had
tried it with the bitstream of the video and audio of the concert, it
would not have worked.
Similarly, while we can currently regulate prostitution without prohibiting all sex, since the reception of sex necessitates attention, our tool for differentiating commodified sex with non-commodified sex will cease to exist. | | | |
> > | The outcome of a weak argument on a false
premise.
In an attention economy there will be no more difference between selling and giving. Thus, everything that is sold will have been given and everything given freely sold. In fact, it can be said that all things will necessarily be commodified, and all people (eyeballs) necessarily become commodities; for what else are we but our consciousness?
Or, perhaps, everything will be available freely,
and will not be commodified at all. You manage to argue right round
everything I've said without actually coming in contact with it.
This passage simply assumes it all away | | Conclusion | | -- JakeWang - 30 Dec 2009 | |
> > | Just circular gibberish, actually, I fear.
Conclusions built by not-quite-logical operations on false premises,
unchecked because you like working at a level of abstraction high
enough that you don't have to ask whether anything you're saying
actually fits the facts, any facts, at all. The two standout
problems are the literalism of an "attention economy" in the
non-zero-marginal cost world of "real" good with only rivalrous
uses— which is total nonsense—and the peculiar and
utterly unrealistic distinction between "sex" and "commercial sex,"
which would have seemed strange to Jane Austen, let alone to a 21st
century grownup in New York. | |
Jake, |
|