Law in Contemporary Society

Self-Narrative and Legal Narrative

-- Originally By MichaelDignan

I. Devices for Legal and Self Narratives Serve a Similar Purpose

In general, human beings find it difficult to leave probing questions about their own feelings and behavior unresolved.

  • This is an interesting point of departure. I find myself immediately doubtful. All around me I see human beings who not only leave all the probing questions about their feelings and behavior unresolved, they leave them entirely unasked.

In order to explain behaviors and feelings that are often very challenging to explain, people create "explanatory devices. " These devices vary; some may have more or less basis in reality than others, and may differ in their predictive power. Similarly, in the study and practice of law, scholars and practitioners invoke legal explanatory devices to explain how the legal system works. Felix Cohen’s Transcendental Nonsense and Jerome Frank’s “Modern Legal Magic” in Courts on Trial are two such attempts. The use of legal reasoning is a convincing (or not) narrative that provides justification for legal decisions, while the court’s procedures for evidence and testimony provide a narrative that explains what happened in well-defined boundaries. These explanatory devices are similar to the individual self-narratives we use to render our own emotional landscapes intelligible.

  • This is the crucial claim. It's a claim of "similarity," which is weak. Whether two concepts are similar is in the eye of the beholder. More importantly, similarity has no value in logical argument: if A and B are similar to an extent, that tells you nothing about A's relevance in explaining anything about B, because the similarity may have nothing to do with the property of B being explained. Like Elyse's essay on repression, this draft now depends on the "similarity" between an intrapsychic phenomenon and an interpsychic social pattern. Jerome Frank's Law and the Modern Mind, a brilliant pièce de provocation presented in 1927 the classic forensic use of the analogy between intrapsychic rationalization and judicial reason-giving, arguing quite explicitly that judging is usually performed neurotically, as is believing in judging.

II. Self-narrative is important for emotional wellness, legal narrative is important for societal wellness.

In the short term, many people find it upsetting to write seriously about an important emotional issue that has affected their lives. As time goes by, however, people can derive remarkable benefits from the writing exercise. Timothy D. Wilson, Strangers to Ourselves 177 (2002). According to Wilson, writing seems to work by helping people to make sense of a negative event by constructing a meaningful narrative that explains it. Id.

Writing is also helpful because it helps prevent people from dwelling on the past. Repetitive thoughts about negative events can lead to depression and feelings of powerlessness without ever helping to improve a situation. Numerous studies show that rumination leads to self-defeating patterns of thought, especially when the ruminator is already depressed: “Ruminators are worse at solving problems related to their distress, focus more on negative aspects of their past, explain their behavior in more self-defeating ways, and predict a more negative future for themselves.” Id. at 175. By constructing a meaningful self narrative, people can short circuit rumination. Writing these narratives provides some objective distance from the subject, while providing some explanatory power that helps to short circuit rumination. Providing a coherent picture of the events allows for resolution of the topic and explains it in a more adaptive manner, improving mood and mental well-being.

Just as

  • With those words, a trick is performed. Similarity is no basis for argument. But these two words use a claim of similarity as though it were a claim of equality. When two things are equal, evidence about the properties of one is evidence about the properties of the other. Oranges are similar to apples for some purposes. If they were equal, you could prove orange peels edible by eating an apple. Here you used a conjunction to achieve a major league act of smuggling. There's no just-as-ness about it.

individuals can benefit from constructing narratives about themselves, people as a collective can benefit from creating meaningful narratives about the way that legal institutions work. Its nether comforting, nor productive, for humans to exist in a state of uncertainty as to the operation of the law. For example, with criminal punishment, people value the ability to predict when and to what extent they will be subject to penalty. In a capricious system where prosecution and incarceration are subject entirely to whim, feelings of powerlessness will inevitably follow.

  • Maybe, maybe not. I do not think you could safely characterize the broad sweep of available historical evidence this way. Inevitability is a particularly strong claim, destroyed by a single contrary instance. Are you really ready to defend every single submission of a counter-example, or can we agree that you've got a second smuggle caught in the floodlights here?

Cohen's transcendental nonsense of legal logic provides a relatively stable framework for analyzing legal disputes. While debate certainly centers on invented concepts, like the personhood of corporations, the concepts can go a long way towards providing a concrete, relatively smooth ground for navigating the rough complexities of real-world cases. Although it appears to take the focus off of the real world, in fact transcendental nonsense helps provide a consistent framework for judges to make ethical decisions. Justice comes from the judge's mind and sense of ethics, but consistency and thus dependability must be rooted in something other than individual people. Transcendental nonsense, then, does for judicial reasoning what composing self-narratives does for emotional sanity: it provides a structure, through which the substance can be utilized effectively.

  • This defense of formalism doesn't cohere logically. How a debate centered on invented concepts can provide a consistent framework to make ethical decisions depends, of course, on what you mean by making ethical decisions. But I consider you to have a fairly difficult job demonstrating for many plausible meanings of "making ethical decisions" that "debating invented concepts" could possibly be any help. In the end, you haven't strengthened the argument at all. It's still just an assertion: formalism is good because stability is important.

IV. Narrative devices are not all created equally: we should strive to improve legal narrative devices.

Various narrative devices can be used to describe the various aspects of the self. Just as some can be more or less adaptive, general narratives about the legal institution can also be more or less adaptive. Cohen’s and Frank’s critical analyses of legal narratives illustrate that when legal logic becomes nothing more than a crutch upon which to base decisions rather an actual guiding process, the result is meaningless debate that obscures rather than clarifies the system. The first step to addressing this problem is acknowledging the important role that explanatory devices play in shaping legal thought. Humans, including judges and legislators, are necessarily subjective and biased beings. Such biases, if not controlled by some universal framework can lead to injustice via a fractured and discriminatory system of applying the law. Thus, just as people need a structure through which to see themselves emotionally to avoid feelings of disjunction, people making legal decisions need structure even if, as Cohen and Frank argue, sometimes that structure looks arbitrary and leads us in the wrong direction. In the vein of Cohen and Frank, legal explanatory devices should be critically evaluated and improved to become as adaptive, and thus, as effective as possible at channeling the legal reasoning substance of the law into something that can be evenly applied to the general population.

  • But this is inconsistent with the prior graf. If merely invented quantities are enough with which to make suitable ethical decisions, why should we be "improving" the narratives of imaginary formal quantities we use? In what way do purely imaginary narratives unrelated to reality differ for better or worse in their helpfulness? About legal formalisms, given your argument above, one could say what Gibbon says of all the religions of the ancient Mediterranean: that they were considered by the people to be equally true, by the philosophers to be equally false, and by the magistrates to be equally useful.

  • Your intention with this edit was plainly to give a clear line to the argument, and to straighten out some particular snarls to which I had called attention. But once you did so you had the real bones of the problem to deal with. This was useful, it showed clearly where the fundamental problems were, which is one of the jobs of the editor. But then you had little to fall back on in solving those problems, and you were more conspicuous in your smuggling once you had cleared the ground around the border.

Navigation

Webs Webs

r5 - 08 Jan 2010 - 22:27:10 - IanSullivan
This site is powered by the TWiki collaboration platform.
All material on this collaboration platform is the property of the contributing authors.
All material marked as authored by Eben Moglen is available under the license terms CC-BY-SA version 4.
Syndicate this site RSSATOM