Law in the Internet Society

Compromising our Right to Privacy

-- By HumzaD - 13 Dec 2015

The “security” and “nothing-to-hide” (NTH) arguments are persistent thorns in the side of privacy advocates. Both arguments attempt to persuade us that sacrificing our privacy is not problematic. Assuming that the loss of privacy entails the loss anonymity and thereby the loss of free speech, both arguments must persuade us that the loss of such freedom is justified by countervailing gains. It is easy to overcome both arguments if we establish that these countervailing benefits are nonexistent, but grappling with the potential sacrifice of our liberty is troublesome when the gains to be had include the preservation of other fundamental liberties.

I therefore contend that sacrificing our privacy for certain forms of mass surveillance can: (1) preserve the right to security through the prevention of crime vis-a-vis the security argument; and (2) preserve the right against false imprisonment through government accountability vis-a-vis NTH. Recognizing thereby that a decision to preserve privacy may be a decision to forego other rights, I conclude that we are stuck with a responsibility to engage in balancing acts that will curtail one liberty, to some extent, at the expense of another.

The Security Argument

Rather than engaging in some grand utilitarian calculation of whether unfreedom is safer than freedom writ large, I posit only the modest claim that stripping privacy in some situations does in fact have the potential to either lower violent crime rates or aid in the the retribution of justice against violent crime, thereby protecting a right to life and security (the source of which is discussed below).

The potential to prevent harm is first evident in the work of a company called Persistent Surveillance Systems, which solves crimes using aerial footage gathered from planes circling cities overhead. The military technology has successfully solved a slew of murders in Juarez and allegedly reduced Dayton’s crime rate by a third. As one would suspect, mere knowledge that Big Brother might be watching makes some criminals think twice. The company’s founder has worked with the ACLU on a privacy policy that seems to infringe only on the criminals’ rights to hide crime (footage is only used to see one-pixel blobs move from crime scene to hideout after the crime).

While the program does not practically seem to infringe upon liberties, it is prone to abuse, and it could lead to more intrusive measures that would prove more problematic to our privacy. But if we take seriously the right to security, this slippery slope argument against such a narrowly tailored program should not be enough to outweigh its potential to prevent tangible harm.

In another instance, surveillance of the police itself has shown that police brutalities are reduced when cops are forced to wear inescapable body cameras. In a clear violation of police privacy, the public plays God to the police conscience to inhibit offensive behavior.

And even when surveillance fails to prevent crime or terrorism, it can lead to the ex post apprehension of criminals. Both the Boston Marathon bombers and the 2005 London bombers were caught through review of CCTV footage. If punishment serves as a deterrent for future crime, this retribution also furthers the right to security.

The obvious objection at this point is that these case studies ignore much evidence that suggests that mass surveillance on a larger scale has no appreciable effect on crime. But there is also evidence indicating that it can. Moreover, though their conclusions contradict, data supporting and refuting the efficacy of surveillance in preventing crime both suggest that more draconian surveillance efforts would lead to greater crime preventions, since absolute surveillance would alleviate the problems of displacement. But analyzing these studies and making a normative statement about whether the loss of privacy leads to safer world writ large is beyond the scope of this paper.

What is instead significant is that these programs unequivocally show that mass surveillance that infringes on privacy does in fact have the ability to further the right to security to some extent. If the loss of privacy is the loss of liberty, existence of these gains demonstrably supports the notion that the choice between liberty and security is not always a false dichotomy

The Nothing to Hide Argument

Mass surveillance and intrusive collection of excess citizen data can also serve a potent tool to protect individual liberties in a world where the PATRIOT act passes the senate 98 to 1 after a terrorist attack. Individual liberties come under attack in the hysteria following such attacks, and the government’s ability to sift through mountains of data could prevent detention, abuse, and persecution of the wrong people, as was the case after 9/11.

With unbridled access to our information, the government would struggle to hide behind “known unknown” type arguments. After 9/11, over 700 men with names like mine were detained for behavior sometimes as trivial as having a roommate that developed photos of the WTC. In a world where the government knew everything about these men, the FBI would struggle to proceed with arguments appealing to the danger of letting the men go because of a lack of knowledge. They would also avoid reliance in the first place on intel as flimsy as the PENTTBOM leads.

Conclusion

Beyond an appeal to the natural right to security, the right to protection from violent crime is guaranteed by the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and its call for “security of person.” The right against illegal detention is a Constitutional guarantee. We therefore have a duty to do everything possible to guarantee these liberties up until the point that this guarantee infringes on other liberties, at which point we are forced to make some sort of value judgment about which is more appropriate to abridge.

In this sense, infringing on privacy is not necessarily the meaningless destruction of an untouchable liberty. Rather it is a necessary evil that we have a duty to contemplate if that infringement can in fact preserve other serious rights.


You are entitled to restrict access to your paper if you want to. But we all derive immense benefit from reading one another's work, and I hope you won't feel the need unless the subject matter is personal and its disclosure would be harmful or undesirable. To restrict access to your paper simply delete the "#" character on the next two lines:

Note: TWiki has strict formatting rules for preference declarations. Make sure you preserve the three spaces, asterisk, and extra space at the beginning of these lines. If you wish to give access to any other users simply add them to the comma separated ALLOWTOPICVIEW list.WTOPICVIEW list.

Navigation

Webs Webs

r3 - 01 Feb 2016 - 17:16:09 - HumzaD
This site is powered by the TWiki collaboration platform.
All material on this collaboration platform is the property of the contributing authors.
All material marked as authored by Eben Moglen is available under the license terms CC-BY-SA version 4.
Syndicate this site RSSATOM